Meeting Newell’s other challenge: Cognitive architectures as the basis for cognitive engineering

نویسندگان

  • Wayne D. Gray
  • Michael J. Schoelles
  • Christopher W. Myers
چکیده

We use the Newell Test as a basis for evaluating ACT-R as an effective architecture for cognitive engineering. Of the 12 functional criteria discussed by Anderson & Lebiere (A&L), we discuss the strengths and weaknesses of ACT-R on the six that we postulate are the most relevant to cognitive engineering. To mix metaphors, Anderson & Lebiere (A&L) have donned Newell’s mantle and picked up his gauntlet. The mantle is Newell’s role as cheerleader for the cause of unified architectures of cognition (e.g., Newell 1990). The gauntlet is Newell’s challenge to the modeling community to consider the broader issues that face cognitive science. Gauntlets come in pairs, so it is not surprising that Newell threw down another one (Newell & Card 1985), namely, hardening the practice of human factors to make it more like engineering and less based on soft science. (Although Newell and Card framed their arguments in terms of human-computer interaction, their arguments apply to human factors in general and cognitive engineering in particular.) Cognitive engineering focuses on understanding and predicting how changes in the task environment influence task performance. We postulate that such changes are mediated by adaptations of the mix of cognitive, perceptual, and action operations to the demands of the task environment. These adaptations take place at the embodied cognition level of analysis (Ballard et al. 1997) that emerges at approximately 1⁄3 second. The evidence we have suggests that this level of analysis yields productive and predictive insights into design issues (e.g., Gray & Boehm-Davis 2000; Gray et al. 1993). However, whatever the eventual evaluation of this approach, our pursuit of it can be framed in terms of six of the Newell Test criteria. Flexible behavior. We understand A&L to mean that the architecture should be capable of achieving computational universality by working around the limits of its bounded rationality. Hence, not every strategy is equally easy, and not every strategy works well in every task environment. ACT-R fits our cognitive engineering needs on this criterion because it provides a means of investigating, by modeling, how subtle changes in a task environment influence the interaction of perception, action, and cognition to form task strategies. Real-time performance. When comparing models against human data, a common tack is to simulate the human’s software environment to make it easier to run the model. Although such a simulation might represent the essential aspects of the human’s task environment, the fidelity of the model’s task environment is inevitably decreased. ACT-R enables us to run our models in the same software environment in which we run our subjects by providing time constraints at the time scale that perception, action, and cognition interact. Adaptive behavior. Section 2.3 of the target article emphasizes Newell’s complaint regarding the functionality of then extant theories of short-term memory. In our attempts to build integrated cognitive systems, we too have had similar complaints. For example, the work by Altmann and Gray (Altmann 2002; Altmann & Gray 2002) on task switching was motivated by a failed attempt to use existing theories (e.g., Rogers & Monsell 1995) to understand the role played by task switching in a fast-paced, dynamic environment. Hence, one role of a unified architecture of cognition is that it allows a test of the functionality of its component theories. Section 5.3 emphasizes the ability to tune models to the “statistical structure of the environment.” For cognitive engineering, adaptation includes changes in task performance in response to changes in the task environment, such as when a familiar interface is updated or when additional tasks with new interfaces are introduced. In our experience, ACT-R has some success on the first of these, namely, predicting performance on variations of the same interface (Schoelles 2002; Schoelles & Gray 2003). However, we believe that predicting performance in a multitask environment, perhaps by definition, will require building models of each task. Hence, it is not clear to us whether ACT-R or any other cognitive architecture can meet this critical need of cognitive engineering. Dynamic behavior. The ability to model performance when the task environment, not the human operator, initiates change is vital for cognitive engineering. We can attest that ACT-R does well in modeling these situations (Ehret et al. 2000; Gray et al. 2000; 2002; Schoelles 2002). Learning. For many cognitive engineering purposes, learning is less important than the ability to generate a trace of a task analysis of expert or novice performance. With all learning “turned off,” ACT-R’s emphasis on real-time performance and dynamic behavior makes it well suited for such purposes. Learning is required to adapt to changes in an existing task environment or to show how a task analysis of novice behavior could, with practice, result in expert behavior. ACT-R’s subsymbolic layer has long been capable of tuning a fixed set of production rules to a task environment. However, a viable mechanism for learning new rules had been lacking. With the new production compilation method of Taatgen (see Taatgen & Lee 2003) this situation may have changed. Consciousness. A&L’s discussion of consciousness includes much that cognitive engineering does not need, as well as some that it does. Our focus here is on one aspect: the distinction between implicit and explicit knowledge and the means by which implicit knowledge becomes explicit. Siegler (Siegler & Lemaire 1997; Siegler & Stern 1998) has demonstrated that the implicit use of a strategy may precede conscious awareness and conscious, goal-directed application of that strategy. ACT-R cannot model such changes because it lacks a mechanism for generating top-down, goal-directed cognition from bottom-up, least-effort-driven adaptations. Conclusions: Meeting Newell’s other challenge. Unified architectures of cognition have an important role to play in meeting Newell’s other challenge, namely, creating a rigorous and scientifically based discipline of cognitive engineering. Of the six criteria discussed here, ACT-R scores one best, four better, and one worse, whereas classical connectionism scores two better, two mixed, and two worse. We take this as evidence supporting our choice of ACT-R rather than connectionism as an architecture for cognitive engineering. But, in the same sense that A&L judge that ACT-R has a ways to go to pass the Newell Test, we judge that ACT-R has a ways to go to meet the needs of cognitive engineering. As the Newell Test criteria become better defined, we hope that they encourage ACT-R and other architectures to develop in ways that support cognitive engineering. Commentary/Anderson & Lebiere: The Newell Test for a theory of cognition BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (2003) 26:5 609

برای دانلود متن کامل این مقاله و بیش از 32 میلیون مقاله دیگر ابتدا ثبت نام کنید

ثبت نام

اگر عضو سایت هستید لطفا وارد حساب کاربری خود شوید

منابع مشابه

Cognitive Architecture and Modeling Idiom: An Examination of Three Models of the Wickens’s Task

Cooper and Shallice (1995) raise many issues regarding the unified theories of cognition research program in general, and Soar in particular. In this paper, we examine one specific criticism of Newell’s (1990) treatment of immediate behavior and use it to explain the notion of the modeling idiom within a cognitive architecture. We compare a dual-task model using Newell’s architecture and idiom ...

متن کامل

Cognitive Architectures as Lakatosian Research Programmes: Two Case Studies

Cognitive architectures—task-general theories of the structure and function of the complete cognitive system—are sometimes argued to be more akin to frameworks or belief systems than scientific theories. The argument stems from the apparent non-falsifiability of existing cognitive architectures. Newell (1990) was aware of this criticism and argued that architectures should be viewed not as theo...

متن کامل

Cognitive Architectures as Lakatosian Research Programs: Two Case Studies

Cognitive architectures—task-general theories of the structure and function of the complete cognitive system—are sometimes argued to be more akin to frameworks or belief systems than scientific theories. The argument stems from the apparent non-falsifiability of existing cognitive architectures. Newell was aware of this criticism and argued that architectures should be viewed not as theories su...

متن کامل

Neuro-ACT Cognitive Architecture Applications in Modeling Driver’s Steering Behavior in Turns

Cognitive Architectures (CAs) are the core of artificial cognitive systems. A CA is supposed to specify the human brain at a level of abstraction suitable for explaining how it achieves the functions of the mind. Over the years a number of distinct CAs have been proposed by different authors and their limitations and potentials were investigated. These CAs are usually classified as symbolic and...

متن کامل

The LIDA Model as a Foundational Architecture for AGI

Artificial intelligence (AI) initially aimed at creating “thinking machines,” that is, computer systems having human level general intelligence. However, AI research has until recently focused on creating intelligent, but highly domain-specific, systems. Currently, researchers are again undertaking the original challenge of creating AI systems (agents) capable of human-level intelligence, or “a...

متن کامل

ذخیره در منابع من


  با ذخیره ی این منبع در منابع من، دسترسی به آن را برای استفاده های بعدی آسان تر کنید

برای دانلود متن کامل این مقاله و بیش از 32 میلیون مقاله دیگر ابتدا ثبت نام کنید

ثبت نام

اگر عضو سایت هستید لطفا وارد حساب کاربری خود شوید

عنوان ژورنال:

دوره   شماره 

صفحات  -

تاریخ انتشار 2004