On eligibility by the de Borda voting rules
نویسنده
چکیده
We show that a criterion for eligibility of a candidate by the set of de Borda’s voting rules in [H. Moulin (1988) Axioms of cooperative decision making] is erroneous and we obtain the correct version of this criterion. Let r(ai) be the score vector of a candidate ai, R be the set of all vectors r(ai), and let R ′ be the Pareto boundary of the convex hull convR. Then there is a scoring s such that a candidate a wins with respect to the de Borda voting rule βs if and only if r(a) ∈ R . Introduction. Suppose the set A of candidates and the profile u of the voters’ preferences are fixed. Let s be a system of scores and βs be the de Borda rule assigned to s. Further, let βs(u) ⊂ A be the set of winners w.r.t. this rule. A candidate a ∈ A is eligible w.r.t. the set of de Borda’s rules βs if there is a scoring s such that a ∈ βs(u). The book [1] suggests the following criterion for eligibility of a given candidate a w.r.t. the set of de Borda’s rules: a winner a has the score vector r(a) that belongs to the Pareto boundary of the set R = {r(aj), aj ∈ A}; see pages 2 – 3 for rigorous definitions. Unfortunately, the criterion in this formulation is incorrect. On page 5 we give a counter-example using the profile u defined in Eq. (1). In Theorems 2 and 3 below we prove the correct version of this eligibility criterion. The difference between the correct statement and the erroneous one contained in [1] is that the Pareto boundary of the convex hull convR must be used instead of the Pareto boundary of the set R itself, here R is the set of all score vectors. 1. Definitions 1.1. Profiles. Let P1, . . . , Pn be electors (or voters) and A = {a1; . . . ; ap} be the set of candidates in some elections. Suppose that every elector Pi has an opinion about each candidate such that the candidates are arranged by the strict order >i : the first candidate in this rearrangement is the most favourable for Pi, etc. This strict linear order >i on A is called the preference of the elector Pi and is denoted by ui. The order ui is given by the sequence aj1 >i aj2 >i . . . >i ajp, where J = (j1; j2; . . . ; jp) is a rearrangement of (1; 2; . . . ; p); generally, J depends on the elector Pi. In what follows, we write down the elements of the preferences ui in columns and thus we compose the matrix u = ∣
منابع مشابه
Complexity of and algorithms for the manipulation of Borda, Nanson's and Baldwin's voting rules
We investigate manipulation of the Borda voting rule, as well as two elimination style voting rules, Nanson’s and Baldwin’s voting rules, which are based on Borda voting. We argue that these rules have a number of desirable computational properties. For unweighted Borda voting, we prove that it is NP-hard for a coalition of two manipulators to compute a manipulation. This resolves a long-standi...
متن کاملOn the stability of a scoring rules set under the IAC
A society facing a choice problem has also to choose the voting rule itself from a set of different possible voting rules. In such situations, the consequentialism property allows us to induce voters’ preferences on voting rules from preferences over alternatives. A voting rule employed to resolve the society’s choice problem is self-selective if it chooses itself when it is also used in choosi...
متن کاملThe Borda Count and Dominance Solvable Voting Games
We analyse dominance solvability (by iterated elimination of weakly dominated strategies) of voting games with three candidates and provide sufficient and necessary conditions for the Borda Count to yield a unique winner. We find that Borda is the unique scoring rule that is dominance solvable both (i) under unanimous agreement on a best candidate and (ii) under unanimous agreement on a worst c...
متن کاملOn the Gap between Outcomes of Voting Rules
Various voting rules (or social choice procedures) have been proposed to select a winner from the preferences of an entire population: Plurality, veto, Borda, Minimax, Copeland, etc. Although in theory, these rules may yield drastically different outcomes, for real-world datasets, behavioral social choice analyses have found that the rules are often in perfect agreement with each other! This wo...
متن کاملThe Computational Impact of Partial Votes on Strategic Voting
In many real world elections, agents are not required to rank all candidates. We study three of the most common methods used to modify voting rules to deal with such partial votes. These methods modify scoring rules (like the Borda count), elimination style rules (like single transferable vote) and rules based on the tournament graph (like Copeland) respectively. We argue that with an eliminati...
متن کاملذخیره در منابع من
با ذخیره ی این منبع در منابع من، دسترسی به آن را برای استفاده های بعدی آسان تر کنید
برای دانلود متن کامل این مقاله و بیش از 32 میلیون مقاله دیگر ابتدا ثبت نام کنید
ثبت ناماگر عضو سایت هستید لطفا وارد حساب کاربری خود شوید
ورودعنوان ژورنال:
- Int. J. Game Theory
دوره 37 شماره
صفحات -
تاریخ انتشار 2008